Prawacana oleh Penerjemah Indonesia

Prawacana Oleh Penerjemah Indonesia

Pamflet ini adalah kumpulan tulisan-tulisan dari sang egois ekstrimis dan illegalist Renzo Novatore. Seorang anarkis individualis murni yang memberontak melawan pemerintahan kristian dan rezim fasis Italia yang sedang bergejolak pada saat itu. Berisikan 15 karya-karyanya yang telah di terjemahkan ke dalam bahasa indonesia, juga tulisan dari Enzo Martucci (seorang sahabat dari Renzo Novatore) tentang perjalanan hidup sang iconoclast Novatore dan kenangannya bersamanya, serta dilengkapi dengan catatan biografis dan pengantar dari Wolfi Landstreicher. Novatore pada masa itu dengan tegas menentang gereja beserta nilai-nilainya di masyarakat. Tak heran jika ia menjadi musuh nomor satu yang dicari-cari oleh otoritas dan orang-orang yang membencinya. Hingga akhir hayatnya, hari-harinya ia isi dengan pelarian dan pemberontakan, berpindah-pindah, menyebut dirinya sebagai pengembara intelektual yang kemudian ia tuangkan di salah satu karyanya. Salah satu tulisannya yang terkenal; Menuju Ketiadaan Kreatif. 1924. berisikan syair-syair puitis revolusioner yang menghentak. Penuh kritikan dan hinaan terhadap pemerintahan borjuis-kristian, peradaban demokratis, komunis, sosialis, hingga kaum proletar yang kemudian ia sebut sebagai katak-katak proletar yang menyedihkan. Ia mengatakan bahwa, untuk keluar dari jurang terdalam pembusukan sosial, masyarakat perlu untuk menegaskan individualitasnya, yang kemudian akan mengangkat manusia keluar dari batas-batas menuju puncak tertinggi kerohanian.

Tulisannya yang pertama saya baca adalah Menuju Badai. 1919. yang saya dapat dari seorang sahabat yang juga menjadi rekan saya dalam menterjemahkan Jeritan Pemberontakan. Ucapan terima kasih yang sangat saya persembahkan untuk sahabat saya Thomas. Dari sinilah kemudian muncul niat kuat saya untuk menterjemahkan karya-karyanya yang lain dan menerbitkannya ke dalam sebuah pamflet. Sebab, sulit untuk menemukan karya-karya anarkis kontemporer seperti ini, dengan gaya penulisan yang khas dan sangat agresif, tanpa romantisme atau moralisme, bisa disebut Futurisme, gaya sastra yang muncul pada awal abad kedua puluh, yang bertujuan untuk memutuskan hubungan dengan abad lalu dan menciptakan gaya baru yang sesuai dengan perubahan besar dalam dunia baru.

Mulai saya terjemahkan ke dalam bahasa indonesia sejak pertengahan tahun 2010 dan akhirnya berhasil saya rangkumkan menjelang akhir tahun 2011. Walaupun begitu, banyak kendala yang saya temui selama proses penerjemahan teks ini. Beberapa terminologi klasik dalam bahasa itali agak sulit untuk menemukan padanan katanya dalam bahasa Indonesia. Inilah kendala utama yang paling sering dihadapi saat menterjemahkan teks-teks berbahasa inggris ke dalam bahasa indonesia. Oleh karena itu, beberapa kalimat diubah untuk mencari pengganti kata yang sesuai agar lebih memudahkan menanggapi, tetapi bersamaan dengan itu saya mencoba untuk tidak meninggalkan esensinya. Pamflet ini juga merupakan revisi terjemahan yang ke tiga dari bahasa itali ke bahasa inggris yang saya dapat kembali dari situs anarchyinitaly. Besar kemungkinan terjadi proses distorsi atau perubahan-perubahandi dalam karya-karyanya yang telah diterjemahkan ke dalam beberapa bahasa selama beberapa tahun terakhir ini oleh berbagai kelompok dan individu-individu. Begitu pun pamflet ini, juga akan kehilangan originalitasnya. Saya tidak bisa memastikan atau menjanjikan kesempurnaan sejak saya menyadari kemampuan dan keterbatasan saya seorang diri.

Menentukan padanan kata yang paling tepat untuk menterjemahkan Toward The Creative Nothing yang aslinya dalam bahasa italia berjudul Verso il Nulla Creatore ternyata tidak mudah. Butuh waktu yang lumayan lama dengan sedikit banyak pertimbangan-pertimbangan hingga akhirnya saya memutuskan Menuju Ketiadaan Kreatifsebagai terjemahan dan judul yang paling tepat dan sekaligus mewujudkan dan merefleksikan teks-teks syair di dalamnya, seperti terlihat dalam sepenggal kalimat berikut ini “The abyss awaits us, we leap into it in the end: Toward the creative nothing”.

Novatore dalam beberapa karyanya menghina dengan sangat katak-katak proletar, yaitu mereka yang terus tereksploitasi dan tertindas oleh kaum borjuis tapi tetap tenang dan mengamininya seakan-akan itu menjadi sesuatu yang semestinya. Tapi, mengapa demikian? apakah ini kenapa Ia menyebut dirinya sebagai seorang anarkis individualis? Seorang egois? atau mereka yang tak meletakkan segala kepentingannya di atas orang banyak, mereka yang memperjuangkan keinginanya atas kehendaknyasendiri.

Ia tertarik dengan teori-teori yang dijelaskan oleh Stirner, khususnya konsepsi individualisme sebagaikebangkitan ego, tujuan tertinggi bagi seseorang dengan mengingat kepentingannya sendiri dankemudian mendefinisikan dirinya sebagai seorang "Individual One". Oleh karena itu, dari tahun 1908 dan seterusnya, ia menganggap dirinya sebagai seorang anarkis-individualis, seorang dengan pengaruh nihilis yang kuat.

Beberapa kutipan khas pemikiran Novatore adalah:

"Saya seorang anarkis-individualis, jadi saya tidak mau dan tidak akan mendukung perjuangan komunisme ateistik, karena saya tidak percaya pada elevasi agung orang-orang banyak dan saya menolak realisasi Anarki dipahami sebagai suatu bentuk kehidupan sosial bagi manusia. "

“Anarki bagi saya adalah jalan untuk mendapatkan realisasi manusia individual. Manusia Individual bukan berarti realisasi anarki. Jika itu benar, anarki tetap akan menjadi momok, jika impian manusia lemah akan anarki sebagai tatanan sosial, manusia yang kuat akan mengamalkannya sebagai Individualisasi.”

Salah satu pendapatnya adalah bahwa manusia, sebagai warga negara dan anggota masyarakat, selalu terancam oleh dua "momok" sosial: hak asasi manusia, yaitu Negara dan Kristus, itulah agama.

Ia menegaskan bahwa:

"Salib Kristus melambangkan KEMUNGKINAN kamu untuk menjadi MANUSIA, sedangkan’ hak-hak manusia’ melambangkan hal yang sama. Untuk Mencapai kesempurnaan yang pertama kamu perlu untuk menuhankan, yang kedua memanusiakan. Tetapi kedua hal tersebut jelas menyatakan ketidaksempurnaan manusia-individual. Ego sejati menegaskan bahwa hanya melalui realisasi ideal manusia dapat naik ke puncak kesempurnaan magis.

Kristus berkata kepadamu: “jikalau kau akan dengan sabar menunggu kesunyian kalvari untuk kemudian memakumu diatas salib, menjadi sosok seperti AKU, sang MANUSIA TUHAN, Kau akan menjadi manusia yang sempurna, layak duduk di sebelah kanan Bapa saya yang berada di kerajaan sorga”.

Dan Revolusi Perancis berkata kepadamu: Aku akan menyatakan hak-hak manusia. Jikalau kau akan dengan tulus masuk ke beranda (gereja), simboldari keadilan sosial manusia untuk menghaluskan dan memanusiawikan-mu melalui norma-norma moral kehidupan sosial, Kamu akan menjadi warga negara dan aku akan berikan hak asasimu, menyatakanmu sebagai manusia.

Tapi bila ada yang berani melemparkan nyala api ke atas salib dimana sang manusia Tuhan tergantung dan meja dimana hak asasi manusia dicatat miring untuk kemudian bersandar pada kemurnian kekuatan merdeka dari pusat poros kehidupan individual, ia akan menjadi seorang penjahat tidak beriman yang akan dibuang ke dalam rahang berdarah dari dua momok sosial menyeramkan: ketuhanan dan kemanusiaan.

Di sebelah kanan api sulfat dan jurang kekal neraka menghukum DOSA, disebelah kiri, bunyi membuat tuli dari gilotin menghukum KEJAHATAN.

Jadi, untuk agama dan Negara, manusia tidak akan pernah sempurna kecuali jika kau memutuskan untuk berlutut di depan dua momok sosial.

Novatore menganggap kerja-upahan hanyalah bentuk yang lebih halus dari perbudakan, dan ia sering berkata, ketika melihat pekerja yang lusuh dibalut keringat dan debu: "Apakah dia seorang manusia?." Jadi dia pikir, dalam filsafat pribadinya tentang hidup, bahwa ia memiliki hak untuk mengambil alih dari orang-orang kaya apa yang dibutuhkan untuk kelangsungan hidup sehari-hari, dan menggunakan paksaan bukan-lah masalah baginya. Ia kemudian menulis:

Aku bukan pengemis […]Aku hanya mengambil apa yang berhak untuk aku ambil dengan daya kemampuan-ku.

Pada bulan Mei 1919, kota La Spezia berada di bawah kendali Komite Revolusioner memproklamirkan diri, yang dirampas polisi dan pasukan borjuis selama beberapa minggu. Meskipun seorang individualis, Novatore (yang masih buron) berada di garis depan Komisi karena ia percaya bahwa hal yang paling penting adalah untuk menyalakan api revolusi di antara orang-orang dan memulai pemberontakan yang radikal menentang apa yang disebut status quo. Ia berkata.

-“Kau menantikan revolusi? Baiklah kalau begitu! Aku sendiri sudah mulai sejak lama! Bila kau telah siap –Oh, tuhan, betapa ini penantian yang tak ada habis-habisnya!– aku tidak keberatan berjalan denganmu untuk sementara! Tapi ketika kau berhenti aku akan melanjutkan kegilaanku dan berjalan dengan jaya menuju penaklukan besar dan mulia atas kehampaan!

Novatore, setelah pemberitahuan yang jelas bahwa tidak ada lagi tempat baginya di masyarakat, memiliki dua pilihan: bergabung dengan gerakan fasis dan menjadi warga negara yang baik, satu lagi domba di antara para domba atau melarikan diri ke Perancis seperti yang banyak dilakukan oleh rekan-rekannya yang lain. Novatore memilih pilihan ketiga: menjadi bandit dan pemberontak, berjuang hanya untuk dirinya sendiri di atas tebing dari setiap lembaga manusia. Tentu saja, meninggalkan istri tercinta, anak dan sahabat-sahabatnya adalah pilihan yang sulit baginya, tapi ia adalah seorang anarkis koheren sejati. Pada musim panas tahun 1922 ia bergabung dengan gerombolan perampok inspirasi anarkis yang terkenal: Sante Pollastro, dan dicari oleh polisi sebagai musuh masyarakat meskipun usianya masih muda.

Novatore menikah dan memiliki dua anak pada saat itu. Pada bulan-bulan terakhir tahun 1918, putranyawafat, Novatore kembali ke rumahnya, mempertaruhkan penangkapannya hanya untuk memberikan ucapan perpisahan yang terakhir kepada jenazah si kecil. Kemudian ia pergi lagi. Selama musim panas 1919, Italia diguncang oleh sejumlah protes besar, pemogokan dan pemberontakan setempat terhadap kebijakan pemerintah yang mendatangkan malapetaka, represi berat dari polisi, biaya hidup yang tinggi dan kondisi menyedihkan dari kaum pekerja.

Peradaban industri kapitalis akan mencapai senjanya, dan ketika saat itu tiba, jiwa-jiwa bebas akan merayakan kegembiraannya dengan sebuah balada dan tarian senjakala.

Makassar 2012

Hidayat

Swatantra@riseup.net

2.11.12

Renzo Novatore

What is selfishness?

I asked about “what egoism means”. I should perhaps also have asked what egoism does not mean. For there are a lot of misconceptions about what egoism is. Religious literature incessantly warns us not to think about our own best interest, but the interest of the heavenly, of Man, and of just about everything else. But seldom is there found any advise to follow exactly this own interest. Why then these warnings against self interest, on and on, again and again? Surely not to counter any opposing system of ideas. For there have been close to none. What then is left to counter but — the individual himself! But to counter the individual is not a position that looks very good, so it has to be disguised, disguised as an attack on some “Deep Evil” lurking in self interest — in egoism. So the common view of egoism is far from formed by observation of actual egoists, but by propaganda in its disfavour. I therefore find it fruitful to list what I consider the types most typically mistaken for egoists, both by critics of egoism and by “egoists” themselves: THE PSYCHOPATH: The psychopath is characterised by a tendency of always being in the right and of manipulating others. He typically takes little heed of the interests of people he confronts. The reasoning displayed by those who identify psychopaths with egoists are usually of the type “He does not care for others — thus he must care only for himself ...”, which sets up a dichotomy without any basis in reality. Identifying an individual pursuing his own interests with a psychopath is a powerful means of keeping individuals “in line”. THE EGO-BOOSTER: Somewhat related to the psychopath, in that he tries to make himself “big” in the eyes of others often at the expense of some third person. But the Ego-Booster cares a lot about the judgement of others. In fact — he depends on it. Getting approval from other people dominates his way of life. His focus is not on himself, but on something else — his self image. THE MATERIALIST: The glutton, the carelessly promiscuous and the one who spends all his time gathering possessions is often seen as the egoist by people who have seen through the traps above. A friend of mine wrote in his thesis on Stirner that these were “vulgar egoists”. They sure enough care for their own interests. But they only care for part of their own interest, giving in to some urge to dominate them. They either care only for the taste in their mouths right-here-right-now, or for the feelings in other parts. They do not satisfy the whole chap, as Stirner wrote. THE IDEALIST: Not too typical, but still — important. Can range from the proponent of Fichte’s Absolute or Transcendental Ego, to the person who has as his sole goal in this life to spread his own ideas. The first of these is not a proper egoist in that the “I” he is talking about is not the personal, individual “I” but — an abstraction, the mere idea of an ego. The latter is just the materialist mentality let loose in the realm of ideas. THE FORMAL EGOIST: The formal egoist is perhaps the most elusively like to the proper egoist. For the formal egoist knows that an egoist looks to the satisfaction of the whole chap. Actually the formal egoist can know more about egoism than the egoist himself. For the formal egoist really wants to be an egoist — and he follows the recipe he has found to the last little detail, and sets out to find even new nuances. There is only one thing missing, and that is his realisation that there is no recipe. Egoism is not a religious or ideological system to be followed by duty, but simply the being and awareness of oneself. Now we have defined selfishness in the negative. How now about the positive; to what degree is egoism positively definable? First of all: What does it mean to “value oneself”, and is this what selfishness consists in? This problematic is in particular motivated by a comment from a subscriber, Jon Newton, in a discussion of whether egoism meant following some personal “axioms of value”. First of all, Jon commented that though underneath all “axioms” of evaluation there had to rest the deeper Valuing Subject him[/her]self, that would in no way imply that the Valuing Subject — as a consequence of that alone — had to have a higher value than even the axiom. Now, how is the above problematic solved, if at all? First, I think that declaring as an axiom that the Valuing Subject is of higher value, or to keep it in some other way as an “act of faith” would be a miss. This would be again — to place the act of evaluation as being mediated by the “axiom” or the “object of faith”. The Valuing Subject is the subject, and viewing something else — implicitly or explicitly — as the subject, is an act of alienation and untruth. This does, of course, tie in with the question of the value of truth, which I will address in an upcoming post. But let us assume that the person in question sees this, and can value or non-value it as he wants. No generality is lost by this approach. So the question is whether a person would or should value himself higher than anything or anyone else. It might be tempting, like so many have done, to say some sentence to the effect that if X is a necessary ground for valuing, the X is necessarily valued — or even the highest of values. In my case, substituting “oneself, the (Valuing) Subject” for X would thereby yield the claim that one should value oneself the most. But I do not think such an attempt via “a priori” judgement would get us very far if we were honest about it. For such an attempt would at best give us that I had a conditional value [derived, instrumental] from my values, and only for a certain limited period of time, given by these values. As an example, I could have valued the propagation of the species above all, and readily sacrifice myself when this goal did so require. All this without the contradiction an “a priori” argument like the above would require. * * * Instead, I propose we ask “What does it mean to value oneself the highest?” or “What does it mean to be an egoist?”. Indeed, what does it mean to “value myself” at all? One answer might be that to “value myself” means to value my existence. But “existence”? Now what is really that? An empty, eternal staring into blankness is still “existence”. But not what I would call very interesting, less even attractive. Something is missing. But what? Now, to “value myself” would mean, I suggest, to value that which makes life valuable to me. That means that when I enjoy a good book — when I do what I value the book for — I do not sit there (ho-hum) valuing my existence, accidentally having a book in front of my eyes; rather it means that through the act of valuing the book, which is what I value, I thereby do value myself. It is almost circular. I “value myself” when I value that which — I value. I value myself when I allow my own judgements of value qua (Valuing) Subject be what is in the end valued. In contrast, “not valuing myself” would mean to negate my own value judgements qua (Valuing) Subject. It would mean to let a Fixed Idea get the better of me and leave its judgement as the final or one instead of my own; it would mean to let the Fixed Idea brand my values as “sinful”, “un-human” etc. and — bow to it. * * * That was the theory. Now what is the practice? Lots of unresolved questions. Good. That’s one reason I created Non Serviam. But this gives a very different picture of the Egoist than what is normally being promoted throughout society. Society’s “Egoist” is nothing more than just another example of what I’d call a “spooked man”; a man who instead of plainly following his own interests — i.e. his own values — follows a Fixed Idea that is accidentally branded “My Own Interests”. Society’s “Egoist” is a charicature who does not pet cats since oh horror! — the cat might benefit from it too, who does not like other people other than as means to gaining material advantage — “for of course an Egoist can see no value in other people, his gaze is all directed at one person” — and who’s got as his prime imperative “Do not give to beggars!” As a contrast, let us take some real Egoist, as described by Stirner: He does not only enjoy people when they are safely packed away in material books, but also gets pretty charmed by the smile of a little baby. He pets cats for enjoyment, and loves to sit for a friendly chat with his friends — possibly over a glass of wine given to this friend. Think about it. If Egoism is not about making life as enjoyable as possible, i.e. about realising one’s values without interference from Fixed Ideas, what is it? Society’s charicature would soon find himself in a logical mess if he thought about this. Not only would he fade away in a Scrooge-like asceticism, but he would begin to wonder why this bugger tomorrow who incidentally identified himself-now with “himself-in-the-past” should ever get a little benefit from himself-now. He couldn’t even get a glass of water. * * * As for ever being able to “axiomatise” my own value judgements. Is it possible? Stirner certainly did not think so. “I create myself each day anew” and “I am the creative nothing” are sentences that express this existentialist sentiment. I lean to the same judgement, and do in particular not see present-day reductionism as a solution to the problem. First of all, I do not think reductionism is universally valid, and secondly, even if it were, our mere biology would probably be of such a nature as to make our values incapturable through fixed axioms at the level on which we normally live and breathe. The above paragraph is of course merely my opinions. I think that most arguments count in their favour, and hence adopt these opinions as “mine” at the present time. I used to be of the opposite opinion, i.e. that reductionism was the truth, but after a discussion with a friend who found reductionism to be untenable, we switched opinions — both of us! Anyhow, even given that for some period of my life my values were of the character that they could be axiomatised: Why should they? Would they ever express anything new in regards to my values? If they did, would not that mean they — contradicted them, and thus had become Fixed Ideas and — false? «The self must become concrete, and this it becomes through the process of action. [...] [T]he abstract man, as only general self, is abstract as long as he is not yet a proprietor. Only as proprietor is man a particular and real man.» — August von Cieszkowski Teleology of world history (ch.3, Prolegomena to Historiosophie)

Mutual Utilization: Relationship and Revolt in Max Stirner by Massimo Passamani*

In the panorama of studies of Stirner there are many silences — silences that, as often happens, communicate more than words. One such silence surrounds Stirner’s reflections on the theme of interpersonal relationships, reflections that form a genuine theory of life together. As is known, his considerations on relationships are contained in that section of The Unique and Its Property entitled “My Intercourse.” Stirner attributed great importance to the description of the relations that the Unique maintains with others, as the vast amount of space he dedicates to the topic shows (it is in fact the largest section in the book). Nonetheless, “My Intercourse” has been and is perhaps the least explored part of Stirner’s work. In any case, it is the least understood; a misunderstanding that Stirner himself already emphasized in the response to the critiques that Szeliga, Feuerbach and Hess had made of The Unique and Its Property. [1] In my opinion, a deep examination of the question of relationships in Stirner means not only studying what may be the most important part of his thought, but also confronting Stirner’s most significant themes from an anarchist point of view (a point of view that obviously doesn’t exhaust their complexity). “My Intercourse” contains his description of property (thus the critiques of the state, of Proudhon and of the communists), associative proposal of the union [2] of egoists (thus the judgment of the party, society and, more generally, hierarchical order), and the distinction between rebellion and revolution (thus the difference between demolition and the reformation of what exists). For the same sort of reasons, it would be useful to spend some time on some of the more important and recurrent criticisms of Stirner’s conception of relationships. In fact, though Stirner’s thought is the object of such criticisms, much of their content could be referred more generally to any conception that radically affirms the centrality of the individual. In Stirner, the awareness is clear that an extreme defense of individuality itself, before being a way of life, is way of understanding. When Stirner, drawing off Protagoras’ motto, maintains that “the individual is the measure of all things,” he means precisely that. One cannot understand his way of thinking about relationships between Uniques, if one doesn’t first understand his way of conceiving the world of the Unique. In the same way, one cannot understand the coming together of individual owners — the union of egoists — if one doesn’t first understand what Stirner means by individual owner. “Everyone is the center of his own world. World is only what he himself is not, but what belongs to him, is in a relationship with him, exists for him. “Everything turns around you; you are the center of the outer world and of the thought world. Your world extends as far as your capacity, and what you grasp is your own simply because you grasp it. You, the Unique, are ‘the Unique’ only together with ‘your property.’” [3] In my opinion, this passage summarizes The Unique and Its Property as a whole. Stirner’s way of understanding relationships between individuals, meaning mutual utilization, is only its logical and necessary consequence. Affirming that everyone is the center of his own world means denying any sort of authority and hierarchy, insofar as they claim to impose their centrality, and imposing a perspective different and opposed to that of the individual, despoil him of his property. Emphasizing the universality of uniqueness (in the sense that everyone is unique), Stirner does not set himself as the center, but as a center. Thus, uniqueness is closely connected to mutuality. When Stirner speaks of a world, he means the collection of relationships that the Unique maintains with those other than himself, be they things or persons. The centrality with respect to the world is therefore centrality with respect to his relationships, and these latter being the “mutuality, action, commercium among individuals,” [4] we see once again how centrality and mutuality presuppose each other. If everyone is “unique” only together with his “property,” then everyone is “unique” only together with his relationships (with his world). The term uniqueness therefore excludes absoluteness, in that absolute — ab-solutum — means precisely the lack of relationships, of connections. Thus the critique made against Stirner that he transformed the I of Fichte into an equally absolute individual collapses. In fact, the Fichtean I, like Feuerbach’s human being, is an essence outside of the particular individual, not the flesh and blood individual, “transient and mortal.” It is a transcendent being that presupposes perfect community among human beings, whereas Stirner speaks of a Unique whose community with others is only thinkable, not real. In reality, we, as Uniques, are irreducibly different. We come to be equal only if we pose a “third,” external and transcendent — like Humanity, God or the State — that mediates relationships between us. And hierarchy consists precisely of this “third”; I no longer value the other for what my relationship with him is, meaning what he is for me, but rather in relation to an entity that contains us and links us together. [5] If everyone, as unique, is exclusive and exclusivist, his existence cannot incline toward community, but rather toward one-sidedness. No longer having anything that unites us, we no longer have anything that separates us or makes us enemies. In fact, “the opposition disappears in complete — separateness or uniqueness.” [6] It is precisely the awareness of our one-sidedness (of having our own perspective) that allows us to rise up against hierarchy, against the order of dependence on which every state is based, and to lay the foundations for a new associative form — the union — based on radically different presuppositions. “Let’s not seek the most comprehensive community, ‘human society,’ but let’s seek in others only means and organs that we use as our property!” [7] In the “reduction” of the other to means, some have wanted to see a defense of exploitation [8], the negation of every form of non-conflictual relationship, the legitimation of a war that opens the way to “collective suicide.” [9] If one instead inserts it into Stirner’s conception of the world, one realizes that it is the only form of relationship that doesn’t deny the centrality of the individual and that is based on real mutuality. The typical form of religious alienation consists in attributing value to a person or a thing in the absolute sense, meaning independently of our relationship to it. The belief in a being that has value in itself and for itself, thus, worthy of our “enthusiasm,” absolutely interesting (i.e., an interesting object without and interested subject), presupposes the ideological “fixed idea” of a hierarchical order. In fact, I can consider a person absolutely deserving of love, respect, etc., only if I don’t consider her for herself, but place her in relation (and thus subordinate her) to a higher being — let’s say God, the state, or society — and consider as “part” of it. Thence, it is not the particular individual in its unrepeatable uniqueness with whom I enter into relationship, but rather the christian, the citizen, the member of society. Contrarily, seeking the value of every thing and every person within and not outside myself, I affirm my centrality in relation to the world, to my world. In this way, “If I cherish and care for you, because I love you, because my heart finds nourishment in you and my desire finds satisfaction in you, this is not for the sake of some higher being,... but out of egoistic pleasure: you yourself with your own being have value to me, because your essence is not a higher being, is not higher or more general than you, is unique as you yourself, because you are it.” [10] The awareness of one’s egoism, thus of one’s use of the other, comes to be the only way of recognizing and appreciating his value, those properties of his that, even though they don’t exhaust his uniqueness, communicate something — however non-essential — about him to me. And being, as I said, mutual use, each individual, each Unique, is the beginning and end of his relational activity. Precisely because, even from a biological point of view, I cannot take as a reference anything different from myself; what is other than me, I can only think of (and for Stirner, thought in its universality cannot grasp the peculiarity of the bodily and momentary I) as subject, but in the very moment that it crosses my path, it exists for me, and all that I seem to owe to it, I owe only to myself. Saying therefore that “For me you are nothing but my food, even as I too am fed upon and consumed by you,” [11] is not the expression of a paranoiac desire to crush (a relationship between “ruminants” as Kuno Fischer described it), but rather a calm affirmation of our centrality and our one-sidedness. It is important to note how Stirner, when he states that “we have have a single relationship with one another, that of usability, utility, use,” he emphasizes again and again the mutuality inherent in such relationships (as opposed to the hierarchical relationship that, posing absolute values, negates it). If I consider the other as “an object for which I may feel something or also nothing, a usable or non-usable subject,” with which to get on and reach an agreement “so as to increase my power through this alliance and be able to succeed, by uniting our forces, where one alone would fail,” I realize that it is not only a matter of a mutual utilization, but also of a utilizable mutuality. [12] The deliberate stress that Stirner places on the usability of the relationships that the Unique maintains with the other only aims to emphasize how in the relationship between individual owners there is a mutual interest in the person and not, as morality and religion claim, a mutual renunciation. Real love, as opposed to idealized love, is a self-interested emotion and not an act of self-denial. In fact, “we want to love because we feel love, because love is pleasant to our heart and our senses, and in love for the other person we feel a higher enjoyment of ourselves.” [13] It is the same love for the other that leads me to “joyfully sacrifice for him innumerable pleasures of mine,” to “give up innumerable things to see his smile blossom again,” and to “put at risk for him the thing that, if he were not there, would be the dearest thing in the world to me: my life or my well-being or my freedom. Or rather my pleasure and my happiness consist precisely in the enjoyment of his happiness and pleasure.” “But,” Stirner emphasizes, “there is something that I don’t sacrifice to him: myself; I remain an egoist and enjoy him.” [14] The charge Stirner makes against all those improvers of humanity — like Baron von Stein [15] — who preach the principle of love is significant: “You love human beings, so you torment the individual human being, the egoist: your love of humanity is cruelty to human beings.” [16] If “every religion is a cult of society, this principle, by which the social (civilized) human being is dominated,” [17] the awareness of egoism and the refusal of self-renunciation can only lead Stirner to elucidate a new form of associative relation, the union of egoists. Once the state and society are negated as historical forms of mediated life together that transcend the individual and are therefore alienated, associative relationships have to have completely different characteristics. The main element is that the individual associates for her own individual interests and not for a hierarchical and extortionist “common good.” For Stirner, society is only an additional product of individuals whose interests are unique. Thinking of society — as Proudhon himself does — as a collective subject, as an “ethical person,” means condemning the particular individual, in the name of a religious general interest, to one of the worst forms of despotism. [18] The Unique doesn’t want to be made the object of collective ends, becoming a tool of society, but rather considers society as one of his means. As B. R. Tucker rightly maintained: “Society is not a person nor a thing, but a relation; and a relation can have no rights,” [19] nor — I would add — can it impose duties. But since, for Stirner, established society cannot block the individual from making value of herself, nor can the future societies promised by socialists and communists expropriate him of his property, the separation from the social order must be so complete and decisive as to “bring about the end of separation itself” and be overturned in federation, [20] in union. In fact, “as the Unique, you can assert yourself only in the union, because the union doesn’t possess you, but rather you possess it or make use of it.” Property only gets recognized in it, because I no longer hold what is my own as a fief from any being, [21] but I myself am to be its source and its self-guarantee. Private “property,” on the other hand, is only a state concession, a fief that transforms the individual “owner” into a vassal; it is the political form of pauperism and vassalage. Only once the “war of all against all” — which isn’t a form of expanded domination, but the calm acceptance of the conflict of interests — is declared, the union will be able to be born as the “multiplier” of individual powers, as a tool, as a “sword” for increasing one’s capacities and thus, since everyone is unique only together with his property, and thus reinforce the feeling of uniqueness. The choice of association must be voluntary, just as the breaking of the associative agreement must be free and voluntary. By associating, the particular individual doesn’t renounce his own individuality, as occurs in society, but on the contrary, affirms it in all its fullness. When an individual needs to unite with others to achieve a specific objective (a need that is not at all contradictory, or better, paradoxical with regards to one’s being unique), what may appear to be a sacrifice — as a limitation of his freedom would appear — is only a deployment of his powers. In fact, not being able to meet all of her needs by herself, by associating he only sacrifices what he does not possess, i.e., she “doesn’t sacrifice a goddamn thing.” To put it another way: not having the freedom “to do it by himself,” it’s not possible to maintain that he sacrifices it by uniting (and obviously coming to an agreement) with others. In each instance, if one wants to speak of limitations as such, what is reduced in the union is freedom (but it’s a case of mutual restrictions not determined by authority and the sacred as happens in the state and the church), not one’s individuality. For Stirner, “the ideal of ‘absolute freedom’ expresses the absurdity of every absolute.” Only one who thinks — religiously — of freedom as an absolute could fail to perceive the differences between a form of relationship that guarantees to everyone the expression of their exclusivity (and doesn’t limit their freedom except with those rules that are inherent to the relationship itself) [22] and a communitarian order which — as something sacred — is based on subjection and the lack of individual self-valorization. Since the union, unlike society, the state or the church has no existence autonomous from the particular individuals who compose it, its duration is determined by the interests of the “participants.” It is therefore a “unceasing coming-back-together” as opposed to the “already-being-together” typical of (and foundational to) every hierarchical relationship. A “taking-part” in a game to which one contributes to establishing the rules, as opposed to a “being-part” of a social order that presents itself as authority and imposes its laws. The union is not only an alternative to society, but also a tool for rising up, for rebelling against hierarchy, authority, the state (a word which Stirner often uses to indicate the entire existing order). Considered both as a relational form and as a counter-association, the union is closely connected to rebellion. If “my egoism has an interest in liberating the world so that it becomes — my property,” [23] the demolition of what exists, the overturning of given conditions, while being inevitable consequences of rebellion, don’t exhaust my incentive for insurrection, which is the only way to affirm my centrality in the world, and thus in my relations. Without insurrection I cannot create relations that are not mediated, by God or by the state, “mutual relationships such that everyone..., in these relationships, can be truly what he is.” [24] Equally, without my egoistic will to rise up, the union against authority and hierarchy ceases to be my tool and ends up becoming — “just as from a thought a fixed idea arises” — a higher being, a party. Only a form of relationship that affirms the uniqueness of the particular individual is able to avoid reproducing the order of dependence within itself. The Unique cannot oppose hierarchy through a means — the party — that is only “a state within the state,” “a ready-made society” for which he is supposed to renounce his own individuality. This battle can also take place with “millions of people together” [25]; what matters is that the multitude is not transformed into the subject, into that “all” which preserves the traits of transcendence and, thus, of mediation. What opposes mutuality — the Mann gegen Mann [26] relationship that, alone, can confirm uniqueness — to hierarchy is not the number, either positively or negatively. In fact, and I think this is very important, a “collective” dimension (in the sense of I+I+I...) with an individualistic character can be created, just like an individual dimension with a collectivist and alienating character can be created. What distinguishes the defense of individual autonomy from the formation of domination is the associative method. But Stirner, when he speaks of the relationship, of the union of Uniques, refers only to the “form” of such relations: a form that is able to guarantee the centrality of each one. “For Stirner, going beyond the ‘formal’ moment means going back to creating spooks, legitimizing domination, making space for the magic circle,” [27] meaning that moment of alienation that gets created in the dichotomy between being and having-to-be, between existence and essence. Precisely by not creating a new heaven, a new mission, Stirner holds that the contents of the union, the rules of play, will be the exclusive property of the Uniques. If Stirner’s “political” dimension can seem like a utopia, it remains, as the relational world of the Unique, thence of a “who” that cannot be described, an “empty” utopia. The one-sidedness, the separateness of each Unique still remains (or rather, only becomes complete) in the union. Thus, one cannot make uniqueness correspond with isolation. The individual who associates is no less an egoist than the one who prefers to “stand alone”; what changes is the object of her egoism. [28] If one unites with others, it is because he finds in their company a reason for interest, for enjoyment. If one prefers to isolate himself, it means that human beings no longer have anything to offer her. “Remaining is no less egoistic than isolating oneself.” [29] The distinction is therefore not between egoism and non-egoism, but, if you will, between a “poor” egoism and a “rich” egoism. “One who loves a human being,” Stirner says, “through this same love is richer than another who doesn’t love anyone,” since she has one more “property.” Stirner’s egoism is thus full participation in life, in relationships with others. Alongside the charge that he wanted to “atomize” individuals, the charge that Stirner, with his union of egoists, limits himself to proposing only a variant in terminology of capitalist society, a mirror image, however extreme, of the bourgeois order, [30] also shows all its inconsistencies. Stirner, after showing the ideological “glue” of capitalist society is humanistic morality (an internal “sanctimonious priest” who preaches sacrifice), maintains that if one had a more aware egoism, one would take into account that “cooperation is more useful than isolation” and that the abandonment of “competition” — that hidden conflict, as mediated by the state — is nothing but a response to a higher feeling of our uniqueness. In the union of egoists, exploitation (“assertion at the expense of others”) is eliminated as soon as the co-associates, equally aware egoists, “no longer want to be such fools as to let anyone live at their expense.” [31] In a careful reading of Stirner’s thought, it also seems obvious that one cannot associate the interests of the Unique with liberal utilitarianism. [32] Bentham’s arithmetic of pleasures still consists of a belief in a thing that is interesting in the absolute sense, meaning a belief in a “sacred” thing. And we know how for Stirner, any behavior toward something as interesting in itself and for itself is always religious behavior. [33] For Stirner, self-interest is not a principle, it is “a mere name, a concept empty of content, utterly lacking any conceptual development.” [34] In the eyes of our philosopher, “the moral system of self-interest condemns the real self-interest of particular individuals, in much the same way as the supposed universality of reason forces ‘private reason’ to submit.” [35] From this obviously incomplete picture I’ve drawn of relationship and association as found in Stirner one can, I think, understand how it isn’t possible to transform the union of egoists into a bellum omnium contra omnes that does nothing but again propose the domination of human being over human being as the sole form of life together. The Unique of whom Stirner speaks is not moved in her relations with others by the “pleasure of being rude” that characterizes Dostoevsky’s character from the underground. What drives her is not at all the need for the impossible of that inexorable appétit d’être that leads Camus’ Caligula to state that “One is always free at someone else’s expense.” Also foreign to Stirner is that fear of death which, in Canetti’s account, the sultan of Delhi is striving to defeat when he decides to raze the city to the ground in order to enjoy an instant of that “solitary uniqueness” that comes from the “feeling of having survived all men.” [36] Stirner “doesn’t defend the power of the individual to dominate others.” [37] since he shows in an extremely significant way that the exercise of domination is a strongly de-individualizing practice. And since “whoever has to count on the lack of will in others in order to exist, is a shoddy product of these others, as the master is a shoddy product of the slave,” [38] domination comes to be a form of individual disempowerment. And this disempowerment is also accompanied by a process of alienation in that the force of the individual gets subordinated to the proof of the inferiority of others. The desire to dominate [39] consists of the pleasure of prevailing over others, i.e., the effort of escaping a condition that one perceives as equality. If, instead, one is aware of one’s own exclusivity, of one’s being irreducibly different from every one else, one can only reject the craving for “superiority” as a homogenizing principle. The power of which Stirner speaks is the capacity to place oneself before others as an individual, without having recourse to the “convenient bulwark of authority.” In fact, one is quite weak (and incomplete) if one must summon (or needs to be) an authority. [40] Only in the negation of authority can the individual reject the alienated life of the docile, usable citizen, the ruler’s subject who leads an existence that moves to the rhythms of service. There’s no need to emphasize how many similarities there are between Stirner’s union and anti-authoritarian associational conceptions. It’s no accident that the anarchist thinkers [41] who have most consistently harked back to Stirner are the ones who have perhaps contributed the most to the description of acratic contractualism. The notion — for example — of “the method of equal liberty” recalls much that is close to Stirner’s thesis of the equal inequality in the relations between Uniques. Drawing on a theme already developed by E. de La Boetie, that of voluntary servitude, Stirner affirms that “When subservience ceases to be, it will be all over rulership as well!” and after proposing insurrection as the sole solution to the “social question,” he adds in reproach: “If the rich exist, it is the fault of the poor.” A few years later, the anarchist Bellagarigue wrote: “Have you believed that up to today there have been tyrants? Well, you are still wrong, because there are only slaves: where no one obeys, no one commands.” [42] Stirner notes how domination and hierarchy, along with (or perhaps before) being a structuring of inter-individual power, are forms of intra-individual alienation, the process of internalizing the “sacred.” It is in social customs, seen as forms of the “compulsion to repeat,” that he identifies the continuous reproduction of alienation. Thus, between individual owners who refuse subordination before any social order — with its customs, its models of behavior — the only possible relationships are those based on the — contrived, precarious, and always changeable — balance between the egoisms of individuals. Associative relations cannot be based on the imposition of a fictitious equality, nor can a higher synthesis be created between the individual powers. Stirner radically negates any theory of the identification of the individual with the collectivity, of the supersession of the individual in the social. Every individual conscious of his uniqueness will always be ready to rise up against any attempt to settle, through whatever form of authoritarian “fixed idea,” the antagonism between individuals. [43] Rebellion, then, is not just a transitional phase from society to the union, but rather an attitude of constant insurrection against every power, against every heaven, that debases one’s inalienable exclusivity. Without a continuous, extremist of one’s autonomy, there could certainly be a revolution, but it would still just be a reform of the existent. At the basis of Stirner’s ideas on relationships, there is the clear awareness of the irreconcilability between the conception of those who hold that only the establishment of order can guarantee liberty and those who instead affirm that from liberty alone can order be born. It is a matter, if you will, of the eternal conflict between synthesis and balance, between authority and liberty. And there should be no more doubt about where to place Stirner in this conflict. [1] Max Stirner, Stirner’s Critics [2] It’s important to not that both the Italian word “unione,” which Passamani uses, and the German word “Verein,” which Stirner uses have no connection whatsoever to labor unions. — Translator’s note. [3] Stirner, op.cit. [4] Max Stirner, The Unique and Its Property, in “My Intercourse.” [5] It’s no accident that Stirner emphasized the mediating nature of the state seen as one of the greatest expressions of hierarchy. [6] Ibid., in “My Power.” [7] Ibid., in “My Intercourse.” [8] M. Hess, The Last Philosophers. [9] Albert Camus, The Rebel. [10] Stirner, The Unique and Its Property, in “The Possessed.” [11] Ibid., in “My Intercourse.” [12] The preceding passages are all to be found in “My Intercourse” in Stirner’s book. [13] Stirner, The Philosophical Reactionaries [14] The Unique and Its Property, in “My Intercourse.” [15] The liberal at who Stirner takes aim in his essay “Some Preliminary Notes on the Love-State.” [16] The Unique and Its Property, in “My Intercourse.” [17] Ibid., in “My Intercourse.” [18] Before Stirner, the American anarchist, Josiah Warren, summarized his thought using the formula of “individual sovereignty” as opposed to the liberal formula of “popular sovereignty,” the foundation of the 1776 declaration of independence. Not randomly. The ideological appearance of domination always revolves around an abstract collective being; thus, the only way to eliminate archism in all its forms is to bring the notions of liberty, autonomy, independence back to the particular individual. The basis of all modern dictatorship is represented by Rousseau’s “general will.” It could only be something concrete if it was the product of all the individual wills. But for Rousseau, the general will is not the will of everyone, but rather something transcendent, right and infallible, independent of individual wills. Appropriately, Rocker described it as a form of political Providence. The Jacobin, marxist and Nazi dictatorships are merely different methods for using the same instrument of power: the cult of the general good. The usefulness of Stirner’s thought for demystifying the hierarchical blackmail of the democratic system seems obvious. [19] Benjamin Tucker, Individual Liberty. [20] Stirner, The Unique and Its Property. In the same way, Warren maintained that the sole terrain on which acratic relations can be established is that of “disassociation, disunion, individualization.” [21] See ibid., in “My Intercourse.” [22] The limits consist in relational, not moral, obligations, methodological obligations, not duties. [23] The Unique and Its Property, in “My Intercourse.” [24] Ibid. [25] So much so that there have been those who, by jerking his thought around quite a bit, have made of Stirner a precursor of revolutionary syndicalism. [26] In German in the original. Literally “man against man.” — Transalator’s note. [27] So writes R. Escobar in Il cerchio magico. Max Stirner: la politica dalla gerarchia alla reciprocità (The Magic Circle, Max Stirner: Politics from Hierarchy to Mutuality), ed. Franco Angeli, Milano, Italy, 1986, page 15. My considerations in this writing are freely inspired by Escobar’s study. [28] Isolating oneself and associating are only different forms of relationships. Even solitude — Ortega y Gasset maintained — is a relationship, in which one participates in the form of absence. [29] Stirner, Stirner’s Critics [30] This is Moses Hess’ thesis, taken back up by Marx and Engels in The German Ideology, and later repeated by (almost) all marxist scholars who are interested in Stirner. [31] Stirner, Stirner’s Critics [32] Marx and Engels portrayed Stirner’s thought as the final, degenerated landing-place of liberal utilitarianism. See The German Ideology. [33] Stirner, Stirner’s Critics. [34] Ibid. [35] F. Andolfi, “Egoismo e solidarietà sociale: riflessioni su Stirner” (“Egoism and Social Solidarity: Reflections on Stirner”), in Nietzsche-Stirner, pg. 163. [36] See Dostoevsky, Notes from the Underground; Camus, Caligula; Canetti, Power and Survival. Stirner’s influence on Dostoevsky’s characters, as well as on Camus’ The Rebel and Caligula, have been pointed out by other authors. For the Dostoevsky-Stirner connection, see R. Calasso, “The Artificial Barbarian” in The Ruin of Kasch; J. Carroll Breakout from the Crystal Palace: The Anarcho-psychological Critique: Stirner, Nietzsche, Dostoevsky; F. Andolfi, op.cit. For the Camus-Stirner connection, see F. Andolfi; G. Penzo, Max Stirner: la rivolta esistentiale (Max Stirner: The Existentialist Revolt); R. Escobar, op.cit. But it seems to me that no one has pointed out Canetti’s references to Stirner. And yet in his way of presenting the figure of the sultan, it seems to me that there is a clear reference to Stirner. [37] J. Carroll, op.cit. [38] Max Stirner, The Unique and Its Property, in “My Power.” [39] According to Camus, a “désir de domination” is what drives Stirner (see The Rebel) [40] Stirner’s refusal of the principle of authority is contained in the essay The False Principle of Our Education or Humanism or Realism. [41] I am referring specifically to Benjamin Tucker, Stephen Byington and Emile Armand. [42] Anselme Bellegarrigue, (The World’s First) Anarchist Manifesto. [43] It seems to me that the distinction between the balance of antagonisms and order based on imposition recalls, if I am allowed to hazard a comparison, the difference between the harmony of opposing tensions of Heraclitus and Empedocles’ harmony, a unity based on the cyclic predominance of one element over the other, of philia (love) over neîkos (strife) and vice versa. *All quotes from Stirner are my own translation. I have completed an English translation of Stirner’s Critics and The Philosophical Reactionaries, though neither has yet been published in book form, and I am working on a translation of Der Einzige und Sein Eigenthum, under the title (used here) of The Unique and Its Property. — W.L., translator https://sites.google.com/site/vagabondtheorist/stirner/mutual-utilization-relationship-and-revolt-in-max-stirner